Regular readers of my blog (I think there are two of you, so I’ll use the plural) will remember that in the past, I have voiced support for the theological system of Molinism (if you missed that post, you can read it here). I’ve even encouraged you to check it out further, and perhaps you have. Recently, I have been reassessing Molinism in my continuing studies, particularly in light of a philosophical framework known as Thomism, named for the 13th-century theologian Thomas Aquinas. Allow me to relate a bit of personal history regarding my studies to introduce you to my current concerns about Molinism.
From
my generally Calvinistic upbringing, I’ve always had a non-negotiable
commitment to the sovereignty of God. God is in charge, and He is unfailingly
causing His plan for this world to come to pass. Yet like all but the most
rabid of Calvinists, I’ve struggled to reconcile this belief with man’s
responsibility to accept the Gospel to be saved.
Why I’m reassessing Molinism
In
my continuing studies, I’ve felt that a stronger grasp of philosophy has been
the missing piece in my overall education. To fill this gap and to continue to
push myself to learn, I enrolled in the Doctor of Ministry program at Southern
Evangelical Seminary in 2020. I was very intrigued by the seminary’s integration
of Dispensational theology, Classical philosophy, and Classical apologetics—all
inspired by the work of the seminary’s founder, Norman Geisler.
I am very intrigued by the philosophical tools and ideas of Thomism because of what they claim to provide. Thomists claim that their system can provide at least the following three benefits, all of which are very desirable in my opinion:
In various ways, attributes such as
God’s omniscience, timelessness, immutability, and others have been modified or
outright denied by theologians in recent decades. The result is a portrayal of
God that is quite different from the historic Christian tradition. Thomism
provides an understanding of metaphysics that serves as a solid foundation on
which to build a theological and biblical case for the traditional
understanding of God’s being—provided that Thomism’s central claims are true,
and I increasingly think that they are.
2. A philosophy to support the claim that we really do have direct access to reality
Philosophy since the time of Rene
Descartes has spawned no end of nonsense. With what has been called “the
epistemic turn,” philosophy has been chasing its tail, seeking to answer the
question, “How can we know that we know?” The basic answer has been that we
really can’t know anything for sure except our own thoughts; thus we really
have no guarantee that those thoughts correspond to the way the world really
is. But Thomism boldly asserts that we really do have direct access to reality.
Its approach—known as moderate realism—begins with the assertion that we
possess knowledge because it’s simply undeniable that we do! Thomism keeps
philosophical study in the proper order—examine reality first (metaphysics),
then assess how we have come to know it in order to discover how we might know
other things (epistemology).
Vast swaths of Christianity today
are plagued by subjectivity. The subjective question “What do these verses mean
to you?” has supplanted the objective question “What do these verses mean?”
Though very few would know it, this situation is a direct consequence of the
epistemic turn in philosophy. Thomism, through its claim about reality
mentioned above, truly does seem to deliver the philosophical goods that are
necessary to make people confident once again that objectivity in biblical
interpretation really is possible.
Molinism in light of Thomism
But
here’s the rub for my theology—Molinism and Thomism really do seem to have a
conflict at a few points. Though these points are admittedly among the finest
of the finer points of theology, if a person is going to speak on such points,
then he must strive for truth in any statement that he speaks and for consistency
with all other statements that he may speak. In that light, I want my theology
to be accurate and consistent, so I’m reassessing Molinism right now on the
following points:
The doctrine of divine simplicity is
central to Thomism. In fact, in Aquinas’ magnum opus, the Summa Theologiae,
divine simplicity is the first attribute that Thomas seeks to prove after
proving the existence of God. Contemporary Reformed Baptist theologian James
Dolezal has described this doctrine about as succinctly (and clearly!) as
anyone can:
The principal claim of divine simplicity
is that God is not composed of parts. Whatever is composed of parts depends
upon its parts in order to be as it is. A part is anything in a subject that is
less than the whole and without which the subject would be really different
than it is. In short, composite beings need their parts in order to exist as
they do. Moreover, the parts in an integrated whole require a composer distinct
from themselves to unify them, an extrinsic source of unity. If God should be
composed of parts—of components that were prior to Him in being—He would be
doubly dependent: first, on the parts, and second, on the composer of the
parts. But God is absolute in being, alone the sufficient reason for Himself
and all other things, and so cannot in any respect derive His being from
another. Because God cannot depend on what is not God in order to be God,
theologians traditionally insist that all that is in God is God (James E.
Dolezal, All That Is in God, 40-41).
To understand this a bit more clearly, think of what we mean when we ascribe goodness to a person. When you say “George is good,” if you really think about it, you can see that you’re really talking about two different things: George, on the one hand, and goodness on the other. You know this because you know that George could possibly be evil rather than good. Since George and goodness can exist separately like this, you know that you’re talking about two different things.
But we encounter something different
when we say “God is good.” In this case, we’re really not talking about two
different things, as if God could possibly be evil rather than good. In the
case of God, what we’re really saying is that God just is goodness.
Goodness isn’t a quality that is in addition to what God is; goodness just is
what He is. And when you ponder it further, we would say the same thing about
God’s other attributes—they just are what God is, leading us to conclude that
these attributes are not separate “parts” within God’s being. That is the
meaning of Dolezal’s last statement that “all that is in God is God.”
The more I understand it, the more I
wish to affirm God’s simplicity, yet Molinism seems to run afoul of this
doctrine. In positing three logical moments or stages within God’s
knowledge—one stage of which does not result until after an act of God’s
will—Molinism seems to create too sharp of a division between God’s knowledge
and His will. It seems to treat these attributes as though one can be active
without the other. In the light of divine simplicity, it seems better to say,
as Geisler does in his book Chosen But Free, that God’s knowing and
willing are simultaneous, eternal, and coordinate acts of God (see pp. 52-53 of
the second edition).
Thomism relies on the metaphysical
insights of the Greek philosopher Aristotle. In fact, Thomas was the first
theologian of any consequence who was able to “compare notes” with Aristotle
after the latter’s works were rediscovered in the Middle Ages. Thomas, like
Aristotle before him, argued that all of existence can be summed up in two
categories—act and potency, or in other words, that which actually is existing
and that which potentially could exist. God, says Thomas, is pure act—every facet
of His being has always actually existed; no facet of God was ever made to
exist, or in other words, caused to move from being merely potential to be
actual. Something that is made actual by another is said to have “passive
potency.”
With its postulate of three logical
moments in God’s knowledge, Molinism seems to say that God has passive potency.
This observation seems especially true of God’s middle knowledge, which is said
to be caused by the future free choices of God’s creatures. Should this be
equated with passive potency? Craig apparently wants to avoid such a notion by
arguing for a conceptualist model of divine knowledge, which he explains as
follows:
On a conceptualist model of divine
knowledge, God does not acquire his knowledge of the world by anything like
perception. His knowledge of the future is not based on his “looking” ahead and
“seeing” what lies in the future (a terribly anthropomorphic notion in any
case). Rather, God’s knowledge is self-contained; it is more like a mind’s
knowledge of innate ideas. As an omniscient being, God has essentially the
property of knowing all truths; there are truths about future events; thus, God
knows all truths concerning future events (Craig, “The Middle-Knowledge View,”
in Divine Foreknowledge: Four Views, eds. Bielby and Eddy, p. 133).
That explanation seems like it could
avoid the charge of ascribing passive potency to God, yet in other works such
as his podcasts, Craig is very comfortable saying that for any choice I make,
God’s knowledge would have been different if I had in fact made a different
choice. That admission sure smells like passive potency, making it problematic
from a Thomistic point of view.
I should say just a brief word about
the grounding objection, since many of Molinism’s opponents consider it to be
the fatal flaw in the system. Simply put, the grounding objection deals with
the question, “What makes statements about the future true or false?”
I had heard about the grounding objection before and had more or less rested in
the reassurances of Molinists that it wasn’t really a problem. Having examined
it a bit more at this point, I must say that it appears to be more of a problem
than I acknowledged before. In particular, Molinism would perhaps put pressure
on us to abandon the correspondence theory of truth (meaning that statements
are true if they correspond to the way things really are), which would simply
be a bridge too far for me.
It is also worth noting that Thomas
argued by means of God’s eternality that He does know the truth about
statements concerning what is still future to us because they are not future to
Him (see Summa Contra Gentiles, Book One, Chapter 67). So Thomism
certainly does have a way of explaining how God can know the truth about the
future.
Contemplating a Change
Well,
if you’ve made it with me this far, I don’t know whether to congratulate you or
encourage you to find a hobby to better fill your time! Really though, if you’ve
made it this far, I suspect you’re like me and you find value in thinking
deeply about theology. Now that we’ve thought deeply about it, I’ll reiterate
that I’m considering an embrace of Thomism. To be candid, some of these ideas
from Thomism have only become clear to me in the last 15 weeks, so I still need
some time to ponder it all. But having read this, I suspect that you won’t be
caught off guard if you see me changing lanes.
No comments:
Post a Comment